Skip to main content

THE ROLE OF LANGUAGE IN LAW, LEGAL REASONING, AND LEGAL EDUCATION



The centrality of language and language structure to legal reasoning has long been recognized by legal theorists. From John Austin’s conceptualization of law as the “command” of a sovereign through Ronald Dworkin’s insistence on the centrality
of interpretation to law, jurisprudence has grappled with the place of language in legal decision making.

 Legal scholars investigating the structure of legal reasoning from a variety of angles seem inevitably to wind up asking questions about legal language or rhetoric and how it works. 

In an interesting early attempt to map the language of an evolving doctrine, Edward Levi showed how phrases such as “imminently dangerous” and “inherently dangerous” took on a life of their own over time in legal reasoning, going through messy periods of linguistic evolution during which jurists themselves became somewhat unclear about the meaning of the obstreperous legal categories.

James Boyd White has suggested that in the language of judicial opinions, judges constitute communities and engage in conversations that can foster or discourage democracy.

And scholars like Patricia Williams and Duncan Kennedy have looked at the law school classrooms in which this language is taught as prisms through which we can see, in crystallized form, the language of law in action—though the landscape they discern is very bleak indeed, reinforcing existing power asymmetries, sexism, and racism.

Indeed, over the years, a great deal has been written about law school education by legal academics, much of it taking the form of a debate over the relative benefits and detriments of particular approaches to law school education.

Ever since 1870, when Christopher Columbus Langdell introduced his new revolutionary approach at the Harvard Law School, law school teaching has had its own distinctive “Socratic method” genre of teaching. Langdell linked this method for teaching with an overall substantive theory of law, predicated on the idea that there are foundational legal principles, analogous to scientific law, that are discernable through analysis of the raw data of appellate cases.

 Although it is not clear to what extent people using the label “Socratic method” are actually talking about the same kind of speech genre,commentators continue to speak of Socratic teaching as the signal approach to law school pedagogy.

 The stereotypic picture of this genre is that professors question students on the cases assigned for a particular class, so that information is imparted not through lecture or explanation but through
an ongoing stream of questions designed to challenge unquestioned assumptions and reveal underlying legal principles.

 There have been numerous critiques of
Langdell’s formalist philosophy and pedagogical system—most notably from the legal realist school of the 1930s, which also pressed for more clinical education in law schools, and more recently from critical scholars within the legal academy.

 However, despite a number of arguably successful attacks on the substantive underpinnings of Langdell’s approach, the method itself appears to have outlasted its theoretical rationale.

Central themes in critiques of Socratic method teaching in law schools have been that it fails to impart moral values, that it imparts the wrong moral values, that it is not functionally adequate even for teaching doctrine, that it causes unnecessary and harmful stress, that it favors white male students, that it fosters inLaw, Language, and the Law School Classroom  civility and overly competitive attitudes, and that it leaves students unprepared for the realities of practice. Johnson, for example, notes that as law schools adopted the Socratic method, there was a shift from the model of lawyers as moral decision makers to an image of law as a technical field of expertise.

 Zemans and Rosenblum similarly note the move away from moral considerations involved in Langdellian scientism. Critical legal theorists like Duncan Kennedy take this insight one step
further, insisting that the shift to technical expertise itself embodied a morality, but in a negative sense.

 In a somewhat different vein, James B. White characterizes current law school training, with its emphasis on “doctrine in a vacuum,” as a failure, and proposes instead a more egalitarian and creative training. Implicit in White’s critique is also the notion of functional, as well as moral, failure: that the Socratic method and accompanying approaches to law school education, when losing the interest and destroying the confidence of law students, fail to effectively impart even the more abstract conceptual aspects of legal training.

 Another longstanding criticism has been that law schools turn out lawyers not equipped to practice
law.This criticism, though it did not end the use of Socratic training, did contribute to a partially successful movement for clinical education in law schools.

Today, some of the most innovative ideas about improving law teaching can be found in the scholarship of clinical and legal writing law professors. Specific critiques of the Socratic method have emerged from psychological, sociological, and educational research. For example, psychiatrist Alan Stone used a combination of personal observation and interviewing to assess the advantages of this teaching method.

Although he concluded that there were some advantages for “channeling group emotions into structured academic inquiry,” Stone also expressed concern about the negative effects of the Socratic method on students’ interpersonal relations and sense of self-esteem, a theme echoed in current
studies of psychological distress among law students.

 Studies have also highlighted the limits of Socratic teaching in reaching students with diverse learning styles,personalities, and backgrounds.99 Susan Daicoff connects the shift to more impersonal
reasoning encouraged by legal training with lawyer dissatisfaction, lowered public trust in the legal profession, and declining professionalism.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

BRIEF HISTORY OF COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY

Another development in the mid twentieth century with a huge import for the development of cognitive psychology was the opening up of a new field concerned with the possibility of designing and then building computers. Building on earlier work that developed a formal, or mathematical approach to logical reasoning, Claude Shannon in 1938 showed how core aspects of reasoning could be implemented in simple electrical circuits.  In the 1940s, McCulloch and Pitts showed how it was possible to model the behaviour of simple (and idealized) neurons in terms of logic. Taken together, these developments suggested something that at the time seemed extraordinary – that the brain’s activity could, at least in principle, be implemented by simple electrical circuits. In parallel with these developments, the 1930s and 1940s saw pioneering theoretical developments in computation and information processing.  Turing, in 1936, developed an abstract specification for a machine (a Turing mach...

TENDERS

  A tender is where goods are to be sold or work undertaken, and the person proposing it wants to investigate whether there are people prepared to buy the items or undertake the work. Tenders are invited which are then considered, and a buyer or a worker chosen from among the tenderers. Some principles emerge, again based on the normal rules of offer and acceptance, but modified to deal with the particular situation of tenders. Single offer tenders A statement that goods are to be sold by tender is not an offer for sale, and there is no obligation to sell to the person making the highest tender. It is, rather, an enquiry into the viability of a transaction. Spencer v Harding (1870) is an example of a single offer tender, where a sale takes place on one occasion. Those submitting tenders make offers, from which a tender may be selected and accepted, forming a contract. There is generally no obligation to choose the highest or lowest tender, or to accept any ten...

COURIER SERVICES SET TO REDUCE TIME AND ANXIETY IN THE COURTS

The legitimate framework in a nation is an extremely bustling one with judges, legal advisors, and court partners dependably in a consistent race against time to meet the due dates.  With their boisterous every day plan, it is related that authoritative archives are gotten or sent on time with customers requesting need and auspiciousness in the meantime.  In the event that there is any postponement or miscommunication at either end, it might constantly prompt further defers which may not fill a definitive need of either party. Legitimate dispatch administrations go for stopping this hole. In reality, this is a splendid business thought for a man who has room schedule-wise to rearrange around and be capable in the meantime. Legitimate dispatch benefit is tied in with conveying or getting archives to and from your customers on time without losing or losing any records all the while.  YOU MAY ALSO: THINGS YOU NEED TO KNOW ABOUT SYSTEM OF EDUCATION IN CANADA ...