A brief history of cognitive psychology Cognitive
psychology did not begin at any one defining moment, and there are many
antecedents to its evolution as a branch of enquiry.
In this section we will
briefly sketch some of those antecedents and try to indicate how and why they
resulted in the development of what today we call cognitive psychology.
However, all written history is necessarily selective and simplified, and a
historical account as brief as the one we are about to give must be especially
so. We start with introspectionism.
INTROSPECTIONISM:
Modern experimental psychology has its roots in the work
conducted in Europe in the mid nineteenth century by such people as Donders,
Fechner, Helmholtz and Mach. When Wundt established the first dedicated psychology
laboratory in Liepzig in 1879, he sought to build upon the efforts of these
pioneers. He took consciousness to be the proper subject matter of psychology.
According to Wundt, physical scientists study the objects of the physical world
either directly or, more often, through observation of the readings on
instruments. In either case, observation is mediated by conscious.
FOUNDATIONS
OF COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY:
Conscious experience that preceded the response. For
example, if one condition in an experiment yielded longer RTs than another, he
wanted to know how the two preceding conscious experiences differed. Wundt was
not concerned with the unconscious processes involved in responding to a simple
stimulus – the rapid information-processing operations that, as you will find
in the following chapters, form much of the subject matter of modern cognitive
psychology. He considered these to lie in the realm of physiology rather than
of psychology.
In opposition to Wundt’s Liepzig school was the Wu¨ rzburg school of introspection. Its leader, Ku¨lpe,
was a former student of Wundt’s, who with his colleagues and students developed
an alternative view of conscious experience and what could be revealed by
introspection. in relation to the topic of perception, although the
protagonists would not have used these exact terms themselves.
Put simply, the
Liepzig school held that the contents of consciousness are constructed
‘bottom-up’ from simple sensations combined in accordance with the strength of
association between them .
The Wu¨ rzburg
school, on the other hand, held that the contents of consciousness are
determined in a much more ‘top-down’ fashion by the nature of the task that one
is engaged upon. Ku¨lpe and his colleagues sometimes studied simple tasks, but
tended to favour more complex ones in which mental acts such as attending,
recognizing, discriminating and willing played a larger role.
Introspectionism
went into a terminal decline during the first two decades of the twentieth
century. The details of the many unresolved disagreements between the two
schools of introspectionism need not detain us here, but it is worth noting two
things. First, the introspectionists developed elaborate classifications of
conscious experience, a topic that has quite recently begun to attract the
attention of psychologists once again.
Second, although
psychologists began to lose interest in consciousness during those two decades,
the exploration of consciousness still remained central to developments in the
visual and literary arts (e.g. cubism and expressionism in painting, and James
Joyce, Virginia Woolf and Gertrude Stein in literature).
GESTALT
PSYCHOLOGY :
The perceived failures of introspectionism provoked a
number of intellectual reactions. In Europe, the gestalt psychologists built
upon the work of the Wu¨ rzburg school and argued that the contents of
consciousness cannot be analysed into simple component sensations.
According to
Wundt, the perception of movement results from a sequence of sensations
corresponding to an object occupying successive locations over time. However,
Wertheimer argued in 1912 that ‘pure movement’ can be perceived directly; it
does not have to be ‘inferred’ from changesin the location of an object. A good
example is when we see the wind gust through grass. Blades of grass bend in
succession but no blade changes location. What we perceive is pure motion (of
the invisible wind) without a moving object. (Modern studies show that motion
perception can, in fact, arise either on the basis of the changing location of
an object or from successive changes across space without a moving object.)
Gestalt psychologists also emphasized the importance of the perception of
stimulus Patterning to our conscious experience.
A tune played in one key on
one sort of instrument remains the same tune when played in another key or on a
different instrument. Since the notes, or the sounds making up the notes, have
changed in each case, there must be more to the tune than can be found by an
analysis into simple auditory sensations. The tune is in the perceived
relationships between the notes, their patterning. Meanwhile, in the USA,
William James opposed introspectionism with his ‘functionalist psychology’.
Sounding remarkably like an exponent of what is now called evolutionary
psychology, James stated that, ‘Our various ways of feeling and thinking have
grown to be what they are because of their utility in shaping our reactions to
the outer world’. These functions of the mind were, in James’s view, the proper
subject matter for psychology. Perceiving and thinking, grief and religious
experience, as psychological functions, were themselves to be the focus of
interest, rather than the evanescent contents of consciousness on which the
introspectionists had fixated. However, James’s ideas were soon to be largely
swept aside by another and more powerful current in US thought, which was
behaviourism.
BEHAVIOURISM:
The founders of behaviourism were driven by various
motives, not all shared in common. Watson, the principal standard-bearer for
the new kind of psychology, was especially keen to move psychological research
out of the laboratory and into ‘the real world’. He was less interested in fine
distinctions of conscious experience than in how people act in everyday life,
and in how they can be influenced. He wanted to see psychological knowledge
applied to education, clinical problems and advertising, and he initiated work
in all these areas.
Not all behaviourists were as zealous as Watson when it
came to applying psychology, but one belief they did have in common was that
psychology should be scientific and objective; and by this they meant that its
subject matter should be publicly observable. Consciousness is (at best) only
privately observable; it is not publicly observable. What is publicly
observable is behaviour and stimuli. So psychologists such as Thorndike, Watson
and, later, Skinner, Eysenck and others argued that psychology should be
scientific in its approach, and should seek to explain behaviour through
reference only to stimuli. The emphasis on public observation wasintended to
place psychology on an objective footing, akin to the natural sciences like
physics and chemistry, and it reflected a wider philosophical consensus as to
the proper nature of scientific enquiry.
SCIENCE AND THE UNOBSERVABLE:
In all human
efforts to comprehend the world there is a tension between, on the one hand,
observable events and, on the other hand, the often encountered need when
explaining them to postulate unobservable theoretical entities and forces,
whether gods or atoms. This tension is
central to science. A key idea in the development of science has been that
knowledge should be empirical, based on experience not on received wisdom or
purely rational calculation.
Observation is one of the touchstones of science,
but scientific theories also refer to unobservables. The explanation that
physics offers for an apple falling to Earth invokes the notion of a
gravitational force, something that is not directly observable. Similarly, in explaining
why a compass needle points to magnetic north, physicists talk of magnetic
fields, and lines of magnetic force. But these thingstoo are unobservable. If
you have ever placed iron filings near a magnet, you will see that they will
move to orient themselves along the lines of the magnetic field.
But,strictly,
we don’t observe the magnetic field, nor the lines of magnetic force, but
rather their influence upon the iron filings. All naturalsciences employ unobservable,
theoretical constructsthat are invoked in order to explain observations. For
example, chemistry appeals to notions such as the energy levels of electrons in
order to explain why compounds react. These levels are unobservable too, of
course. So, the fact that a discipline is committed to explaining observed
behaviour by reference to hypothesized, unobservable constructs does not in
itself render the discipline unscientific.
But to find scientific acceptance,
unobservable constructs have to be seen to do useful theoretical work. When
Newton proposed the notion of a gravitational force, certain critics
immediately accused him of introducing a mystical notion into ‘the new
science’. Newton’s ideas gained acceptance only because they met other scientific
criteria – such as elegance,simplicity and rigour – and because the concept of
gravitation, despite its somewhat mysterious nature, had a wide range of
application. Gravitation explained not just the fall of objects to the ground
but also the rhythm of the tides and the movements of the planets. It could
also be precisely formulated mathematically as an inverse square law: the
attraction between any two bodies varies as the square of the distance between
them. In other words, the willingness of the scientific community to
countenance a hypothetical unobservable depends on how useful it is judged to
be on a range of criteria. Science has had to live with the necessity for
unobservables.
But acceptance through necessity is not liking, and science
always receives a boost when a technical breakthrough for the first time brings
a previously unobserved entity into the realm of observation. For example,
Mendel postulated ‘units of heredity’ on the basis of his plant-breeding
observations, but these ideas were felt to be on a firmer footing once new
technology made it possible to see chromosomes and genes.
Thus,scientists are
forced somewhat grudgingly to accept the need for postulating unobservables.
And because science – like all human institutions – is subject to swings of
fashion, the willingness to countenance unobservable theoretical entities
fluctuates over time. For reasons which we are unable to describe here, but
which were rooted in the growing crisis of classical physics that would
culminate in the birth of quantum theory and relativity theory, the late
nineteenth and early twentieth century was a period during which scientists
were particularly intolerant of unobservables. The importance of observation
became enshrined in the assumption known as operationism. This is the idea that
theoretical concepts are only meaningful to the extent that they can be
exhaustively analysed in terms of thingsthat can be observed.
Back to behaviourism :
The bias against unobservables affected all the
traditional sciences and also the newer, aspirant scientific disciplines such
as physiology and psychology. The introspectionists, with their ‘observations’
of consciousness, had responded to it, but the intellectual climate seems to
have been especially suited to propagating an emphasis on what could be
publicly observed. With the decline of introspectionism, behaviourism was taken
up enthusiastically, first in the USA and then more widely. While behaviourists
could, perhaps, concede the existence of consciousness while arguing that it
was not appropriate for scientific study, at least some of them felt that
operationism committed them to the stronger claim that talk of consciousness
was not even meaningful. Of course, behaviourism has never been a single view,
and since the time of Watson and Thorndike behaviourists of various hue have
modified their positions.
Skinner, for example, conceded that internal mental
events, including conscious experiences, might exist (indeed they were
construed as forms of covert behaviour). But despite this rejection of
operationism, even Skinner still thought that talk of internal events should be
avoided within a scientific psychology. You might think that avoiding talk of
internal events might make it impossible to explain many, or even most,
psychological phenomena. However, behaviourists were concerned to show how even
complex phenomena might be understood in terms of principles of learning, with
behaviour seen as made up of learned responses to particular stimuli.
One view
of language production, for example, was that the utterance of a word could be
seen as a learned response. The utterance of a whole sentence could be seen as
involving a chain of stimulus–response pairs, in which each response (the
utterance of a word) also serves as the stimulus that leads to the production
of the next response (the next word). Despite the possibility of giving
behaviourist explanations of complex activities such as the utterance of a
sentence, behaviourists tended not to offer accounts of what we now refer to as
higher mental processes – processes such as producing and understanding
language, planning, problem solving, remembering, paying attention,
consciousness and so on. As the years passed, however, some psychologists came
to see this as a major failing.
THE RETURN OF THE COGNITIVE:
In 1948, at a meeting known as the Hixon symposium, Karl
Lashley gave a talk entitled ‘The problem of serial order in behaviour’
(Lashley, 1951). In this, he gave prominence to the problems posed for
behaviourist accounts by complex actions in which behaviour segments are
somehow linked together in a sequence, and where two segments depend upon one
another, even though they may be separated by many intervening segments. Language,
as you might have guessed, provides a prime example.
In fact, the last sentence
illustrates the point nicely: when I came to write the word ‘provides’ in the
previous sentence I chose to end it with the letter ‘s’. I did so, of course,
because this verb has to agree grammatically with the singular noun ‘language’,
the subject of the sentence. In my actual sentence, these two words were
separated by a clause, and so my action at the time of writing the word
‘provides’ depended upon a much earlier behaviour segment – my writing of the
word ‘language’. Lashley argued that since the production of some words in a
sequence could be shown to depend upon words produced much earlier, the simple
view that each word is the stimulus that produces the subsequent word as a
response could not properly explain language production.
He also argued that
many behaviour sequences are executed simply too rapidly for feedback from one
segment to serve asthe trigger for the next. He cited examples such as the
speed with which pianists and typists sometimes move their fingers, or with
which tennis players adjust their whole posture in response to an incoming fast
service. Lashley’s alternative to the chaining of behaviour segments was to
suppose that complex sequences are planned and organized in advance of being
initiated.
Lashley’s view that behaviourism could not properly
explain how people produce (or comprehend) language was later reinforced by a
review of Skinner’s book Verbal Behavior (1957) by the linguist Noam Chomsky
(1959). Chomsky argued, contra behaviourism, that language could not be thought
of as a set of learned responsesto a set ofstimulus events. His argument had a
number of different aspects.
For example, he argued that children seem to
acquire their first language too effortlessly – if you have tried to learn a
second language you can perhaps testify to the difference between learning a
first and learning a second language. While the latter seems to require
intensive and effortful study, the former is something that pretty much
everyone does without the need for formal schooling. He also argued that if the
behaviourists were right, then exposing children to impoverished or
ungrammatical language should hinder their learning of the correct stimulus–
response relationships.
Yet studies show that much of the speech to which young
children are exposed is indeed ungrammatical and otherwise impoverished, and
this in no way preventsthem from learning the grammar of their native tongue.
Similarly, he argued that general intelligence ought to influence the learning
of stimulus– response relationships. Again, however, intelligence does not seem
to influence whether or not children learn the underlying grammatical rules of
their language.
Chomsky presented many other arguments to the same effect, and
though many of these have been thought to be contentious, his position was
extremely influential in setting up an alternative, cognitive conception of
language. Most significantly, Chomsky proposed that language is rule-based and
that, far from children learning language by learning how to respond to
particular stimuli, their acquisition of language involves acquiring its
rule-base. On this view, my being able to write grammatical sentences involves
deploying my (generally implicit, or unconscious) knowledge of the rules of
language.
In referring to such implicit knowledge, Chomsky proposed that an
understanding of how people produce, comprehend or acquire language will
necessarily involve reference to something that cannot be directly observed –
their knowledge of the underlying rules, or organization, of the language.
Although this emphasis on the role of planning, organization and rules in the
generation of behaviour was to be hugely influential from the 1950s onwards,
these ideas were certainly not new to psychology.
As mentioned previously, the
gestalt psychologists had drawn attention earlier in the century to the
importance of patterning, or organization, for perception, and the same point
was also made in relation to action. Someone who haslearned to sing or hum a tune
can very probably manage to whistle it thereafter. Yet singing, humming and
whistling call for very different sequences of muscle movements. This indicates
that learning a tune must involve learning a set of abstract relationships
between notes which can be instantiated as any of a variety of muscular
productions.
A similar idea, that what is learned must often be more abstract
than straightforward stimulus–response connections, was also expressed by the
school of ‘cognitive behaviourists’ associated with Tolman (1932). Rats that
had learned, for example, repeatedly to turn left in a maze to find food were
shown to swim left when the maze was flooded. Since the muscle movements of
running and swimming are completely different from one another, the rats must
clearly have learned something more abstract than a particular chain of
muscular responses.
Even before the writings of the gestalt psychologists or
the work of Tolman, psychologists studying the acquisition of skills had
realized the importance of planning and organization for the production of
skilled behaviour, such as in morse telegraphy or typing (Bryan and Harter,
1899). At the time of the Hixon symposium, therefore, there were already
existing traditions within psychology upon which the renewed interest in the
planning and structure of behaviour could draw.
And, of course, the
intellectual climate of the mid twentieth century was changing rapidly in many
other ways too. New technologies were influencing the ability of scientists to
conceptualize the workings of complex systems. One of the most crucial issues
related to the type of causal explanation that is appropriate to explain the
behaviour ofsuch a system.
Purposive, or teleological, explanations had been
taboo in Western science since the time of thinkers such as Galileo and Newton.
Where, for example, an ancient Greek philosopher might have said that a stone
falls to earth ‘in order to’ reach its natural resting place at the centre of
the earth (which was also the centre of the Greek universe), Newton said that
the stone falls because it is acted upon by the force of gravity.
The strategy
of explaining phenomena in terms of causes that precede and ‘push’ their
effects, rather than in terms of goals, or final states, towards which events
are ‘pulled’, had proved highly successful in the physicalsciences. The move
from goal-directed, purposive explanations to mechanical cause-effect
explanations was usually considered to be a move from prescientific, animistic
thinking to proper scientific thinking.
Behaviourism was, and still is, an
attempt to bring psychology into step with this way of analysing phenomena. A
strict emphasis on an organism’s history of conditioning allows an explanation
of behaviour in terms of prior causes rather than of future goals. However, the
development of progressively more complex artificial devices started to call
into question the universal applicability of explanations in terms only of
prior causes. It became increasingly clear that, while the functioning of the
mechanical parts of any such system can be explained in cause-effect terms,
such explanations will never capture the function (or purpose) of the whole
system. Central to the new kind of apparently purposive machines (known as
servomechanisms) was a reliance on feedback loops.
Feedback is information
about the match or mismatch between a desired goal-state and an existing state
of affairs. The classic example is the domestic central heating system, in
which the thermostat setting selected by the householder is the goal-state and
the temperature measured by an air thermometer is the existing state. The two
are compared mechanically. If the existing temperature is less than the desired
temperature, this negative feedback is transmitted to the boiler controls
causing the boiler to be switched on. The boiler continues to fire until
information has been fed back to the boiler controls that the discrepancy
between the actual and desired temperatures has been eliminated. The system as
a whole exhibits a simple but dynamic behaviour, with the boiler turning on and
off in a manner that maintains room temperature at or about the desired level.
Importantly, the function of maintaining a steady temperature cannot be
localized to any one component of the heating system, such as the thermostat,
the thermometer, the boiler or its controls, but is a property of the system –
as a whole.
Far more complicated servomechanisms with more complex feedback
controls were also being developed. Anti-aircraft gunnery may not seem very
pertinent to an understanding of animal and human behaviour, but it was partly
as a result of working on gunnery problems in the Second World War that the
mathematician Norbert Weiner developed the notion of ‘cybernetics’, the science
ofself-governing, or goal-directed, systems. Accurate anti-aircraft gunnery
requires that a projectile is fired, and timed to explode, not at the present
location of the target aircraft but at its future location.
This means not only
predicting the future position of the plane but also rotating the gun so it
faces in the appropriate direction and with the correct elevation. Clearly,
humans successfully extrapolate flight paths and aim at future positions when,
for example, shooting game birds. However, for planes flying at ever greater
heights and speeds, calculation of the necessary trajectory of the projectile
exceeds human capabilities and must be computed automatically. Moreover, using motors
to move a gun weighing many tons is a very different matter from moving a
shotgun, or indeed a bow and arrow, held in your arms.
Although we are mostly
unconscious of it, normal bodily movement is based upon continuous muscle,
tendon and visual feedback about how the movement is proceeding. Unless similar
feedback is designed into the gun control system, the swinging anti-aircraft
gun may easily undershoot or overshoot the intended position, particularly as,
depending on the air temperature, the grease packed round the mechanism will be
more or less ‘stiff’.
Apply too little power and the gun will undershoot the
intended position, a second push will be required and the gun will ‘stutter’
towards its position. Apply too much force and the gun will overshoot, and will
have to be pulled back, in what can turn into a series of increasingly wild
oscillations.
Engineers discovered that the smoothest performance was achieved
by using feedback loops to dynamically control the turning force applied to the
gun. Weiner, and other cyberneticists such as Ashby, recognized the importance
of feedback and self-correction in the functioning of these new and complex
technological devices, and they also saw analogies with complex natural
systems. Weiner drew parallels between the effects of certain neurological
conditions and damage to the feedback control of behaviour. For example, the
tremors observed in Parkinsonian patients were likened to the oscillations of
an anti-aircraft gun when its movement is insufficiently ‘damped’ by feedback
control. An important intellectual leap for cognitive psychology came with the
realization that just the same kind of analysis can be applied at any level of
behavioural control. In other words, it is not just automatic homeostatic
functions or unconsciously executed movements that can be analysed in terms of
feedback loops but any function/behaviour from the wholly non-conscious to the
fully conscious and intended. Miller et al. (1960) developed the notion of
feedback control into the hypothesis that behaviour (of animals, humans or
machines) can be analysed into what they called TOTE units. TOTE stands for
Test-Operate-Test-Exit. A test is a comparison between a current state and a
goal-state. If a discrepancy is registered, some relevant operation intended to
reduce the discrepancy will be performed (e.g. switch on the boiler). A second
test, or comparison, is then conducted. If a discrepancy remains, the operation
can be repeated, followed by another test. If the discrepancy has been
eliminated, the system exits the TOTE unit. Miller et al. conceived of the TOTE
unit as an advance on the conditioned reflex notion of Pavlov and the
conditioned response notion of Watson and Skinner, both of which can be
conceptualized as TOTEs.
The aim wasto develop a unit of analysis of behaviour
that could apply to everything from a dog’s conditioned salivatory response to
deliberate, planned action. The TOTE provides a basic pattern in which plans
are cast; the test phase specifies what knowledge is necessary for a comparison
to be made, and the operation phase specifies what the organism does about the
outcome of the comparison. Although this scheme makes it possible to talk about
purposive behaviour, and about unobservable goals and comparison operations,
there is continuity from behaviourism. Cognitive psychology generally attempts
to retain the scientific rigour of behaviourism while at the same time escaping
from the behaviouristic restrictions in relation to unobservables.
An important
property of TOTEs is that they can be nested within hierarchies. The operation
segment of any TOTE can itself be composed of one or more TOTE units. For
example, the TOTE for starting the car might be nested within the operation of
a larger TOTE for driving to the shops, which might itself be nested within a
still larger unit having the goal of buying a present. This nesting of feedback
loop units provides a way to conceptualize how behaviour can be complexly
structured. In this scheme, moment-to-moment control of behaviour passes in
sequence between a series of TOTE goal-states, with the TOTE units themselves
nested in hierarchies.
Miller et al. explicitly likened this ‘flow of control’
of behaviour to the way in which control in a computer program switches in
orderly fashion from command line to command line as the execution of any
particular subroutine is completed. (Note: what ‘flows’ around a TOTE can be
energy, information or, at the highest level of conceptual abstraction,
control.)
Comments
Post a Comment